Umberto Eco: Some remarks on a New Realism

8.8.13

Το παρακάτω κείμενο διανεμήθηκε από τους διοργανωτές του 23ου Παγκόσμιου Συνεδρίου Φιλοσοφίας που λαμβάνει χώρα αυτές τις μέρες στην Αθήνα ως η ομιλία του Ουμπέρτο Έκο.

In the last two years some symposia (for instance in New York, Turin and Bonn) have been devoted to the problems of a New realism. In at least one of these occasions I started my communication by expressing a certain perplexity. Is really there a New Realism? The following remarks will outline my prudent opinions about this question.

In the course of my philosophical carrier I was informed about an Old or Strong Realism, mainly because my doctoral dissertation was on the aesthetics of Thomas Aquinas and...



...the main problem of that research was not only what beauty was for Aquinas but rather by which cognitive mechanisms we perceive beautiful objects as such – taking for granted that these objects are really in front of us and are not a figment of our imagination.

Aquinas was certainly an old realist and, as we could say today, an External Realist: for him the world is there outside us, and it is such as it is independently of our knowledge. But Aquinas was also advocating a correspondence theory of truth: we are able to know the world as our mind were its mirror, by adaequatio rei et intellectus. Such a kind of realism was extolled by many other philosophers and what always flabbergast me is that the same position was also maintained by Lenin in his Materialism and empiriocriticism. Aquinas was not certainly a Marxist and it seems hard to believe that Lenin was a Thomist, but it simply means that the ideas of the Old Realism were circulating during the centuries among various thinkers.

In opposition to the Old or Strong Realism I met during my life various forms of Temperate Realism, from Holism and Ontological Relativity to Internal Realism. But at this point it would still be embarrassing to recognize and define a New Realism.

If I had to explain the attempts to propose a New Realism to a student I would say that the appeal to a so-called new realism is a way to react to so-called post-modern philosophy. But there we are facing a new conundrum: I confess (and I wrote at least thirty years ago about that) that I never clearly understood what is the philosophical post-modernism, since it has nothing to do neither with the literary post-modernism of John Barth, Donald Barthelme and Leslie Fiedler nor with the architectural post-modernism of Charles Jenks or Robert Venturi.

The literary or architectural post-modernism was a way to react to the Modern conceptions, mainly those of the avant-gardes of the 20th century: the post-modern artists were trying to liquidate the refusal of the past tradition, returning to a sort of revisiting classic heritage and retelling it under many forms of ironical uotations.

If so, what had these artistic forms of post-modernism to do with the so-called philosophical post-modernism extolled by philosophers like Lyotard? Certainly the post-modern philosophies celebrated the end of the Great Narrations, of a transcendental notion of meaning and truth, welcoming multiplicity and
disenchantement, advocating forms of fragmented or .weak. thought, but it seems to me that these currents were not directly concerned with the problem of realism. As a matter of fact your thought can be polymorphous and disenchanted, you can give up with the Global Narration in order to cultivate only local forms of descripton, without casting in doubt the existence of an external world that stands in front of your
inevitably ―weak. interpretations. Simply you can be philosophically post-modern by assuming that we cannot have a comprehensive and global vision of an unattainable Ding als sich. In this sense a post-modern philosophy is simply a Kantism without the guarantee of a transcendental form of knowledge. The difference is certainly very important but it cannot eliminate the ghost of a Thing in Itself.

In any case we must admit that the most radical form of post-modernism is represented by deconstruction, that is, a typical American commodity produced on French license. Now, when I try to reduce these philosophical currents to a simple and recognizable model, I only find Nietzsche‘ statement by which there are no facts but only interpretations.

I do not think that even the most fundamentalist among deconstructionists really thinks that there are no facts at all, since to carry out an interpretation one must have something to interpret, and if the series of interpretation has no final terminus ad quem it must have at least a terminus a quo – a starting point that, however matters


stand, we can call a fact. Deconstructionists simply assume, in a Nietzschean vein, that we know facts only through our interpretations, and by knowing only interpretations and interpretations of interpretations we‘ll be never in the condition of recognizing the Thing in Itself – reduced to a sort of ghost that vanishes as far our
interpretations keep going on.

In a debate held in 1990 at Cambridge University, with regard to the existence or otherwise of textual criteria of interpretation, Richard Rorty - broadening the discourse to include criteria of interpretation of things that are in the world - denied that the use made of a screwdriver to tighten screws is imposed by the object itself, since we can also use it to open a package. Thus the ―nature. of the screwdriver is imposed by our subjectivity.

In the oral debate Rorty also alluded to the right we would have to interpret a screwdriver as something useful to scratch our ears with. To be honest, in the printed version of the debate, Rorty eliminated the allusion to ear scratching. Evidently he had interpreted it as a simple boutade, an off the cuff remark made in the course of the conversation, and therefore I abstain from attributing this no longer documented
example to him. But if Rorty did not use it, someone else might and therefore my counter objection is still valid, and I reconfirm it in the light of the notion of affordance (in the sense of Gibson but also in the sense of Prieto‘s notion of pertinence).

A screwdriver can serve also to open a package (given that it is an instrument with a cutting point, easy to use in order to exert force on something resistant); but it is inadvisable to use it for rummaging about in your ear, precisely because it is sharp, and too long to allow the hand to control the action required for such a delicate operation; and so it would be better to use a light stick with a wad of cotton wool at its tip.

It suffices to imagine a possible world in which there is only a hand, a screwdriver and an ear (and at most a package and a screw) for the argument to acquire all its ontological value: there is something in the conformation both of my body and of the screwdriver that prevents me from interpreting the latter at my whim.


Certainly post-modernists would say that neither them nor the most fundamentalists among deconstructionists have never denied the existence of the table where they were putting their screwdriver. They would simply say that that table become an object of knowledge only in so far as it is interpreted as a desk, a chair, a
dining table, a support for a surgical intervention, or as a four legged wooden object, a mere ensemble of atoms, and even as raft in case of shipwreck. Obviously I agree but my objection is that this table cannot be interpreted as a vehicle which can be used to travel from Athens to Thessaloniki. The problem is that such severe limitation tells us that the table can be interpreted (and known) in many ways (including those that its
producer was not thinking of), but not in whichever way.

But let we return to the Nietzsche‘s text which originated the idea that there are no facts but only interpretations

In On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral Sense Nietzsche says that, since nature has thrown away the key, the intellect plays with fictions that it calls truth, or a system of concepts, based on the legislation of language. We think we are talking about (and knowing) trees, colors, snow and flowers, but they are metaphors that do not correspond to the original essences. Every word immediately becomes a concept, draining away with its pallid universality the differences between fundamentally unequal things: so we believe that compared to the multiplicity of individual leaves there exists a primordial leaf ―on the model of which all leaves have supposedly been woven, drawn, circumscribed, colored, wrinkled, and painted, but by clumsy hands,
so that no example emerges correctly and reliably as a true copy of the original form.. It is difficult for us to admit that birds or insects perceive the world differently from us, and it makes no sense either to say which perception is the correct one, because this would call for that criterion of ―exact perception. that does not exist, because ―nature is acquainted with no forms and no concepts, and likewise with no species,
but only with an X which remains inaccessible and undefinable for us..

Truth, then (and I still quote Nietzsche), becomes ―a movable army of metaphors, metonymies, and anthropomorphisms,. produced poetically, only to become fossilized into knowledge, ―illusions which we have forgotten are illusions, coins whose images has been rubbed away and are now considered simply as metal and no longer as coins. We thus become accustomed to lying according to convention, having reduced the metaphors to schemata and concepts. And hence a pyramidal order of castes and ranks, laws and demarcations, entirely constructed by language, an immense ―Roman columbarium. of concepts, the graveyard of intuition.

This is a fascinating account of how the edifice of language regiments the landscape of the world, but Nietzsche fails to consider two intuitively evident phenomena. One is that, if we adapt ourselves to the constrictions of the columbarium, we can still manage to give some kind of account of the World (if
someone goes to see a doctor and tells him he has been bitten by a dog, the doctor knows what sort of injection to give him, even if he is not familiar with the particular dog that bit him). The other is that every now and then the World forces us to adapt the columbarium, or even to choose an alternative model to the columbarium (which is at the end of the day the problem of the revolution of cognitive paradigms).

Nietzsche acknowledged the existence of natural constrictions but these constrictions seemed to him to be ―terrible forces. that constantly press upon us, countering ―scientific. truths with other truths of a different nature. He evidently refused to recognize them by conceptualizing them in their turn, given that it is in
order to escape them that we have wrought, by way of a defense, our conceptual suit of armor. To change these terrible forces would be possible, but only in the form of a permanent poetic revolution: ―If each us had a different kind of sense perception — if we could only perceive things now as a bird, now as a worm, now as a plant, or if one of us saw a stimulus as red, another as blue, while a third even heard the same
stimulus as a sound — then no one would speak of such a regularity of nature.

Therefore, art (and with it myth) ―continually confuses the conceptual categories and cells by bringing forward new transferences, metaphors, and metonymies. It continually manifests an ardent desire to refashion the world that presents itself to waking man, so that it will be as colorful, irregular, lacking in results
and coherence, charming, and eternally new as the world of dreams..


If these are the premises, our first option would be to reject what surrounds us (and the way in which we vainly try to reduce it to order) and take refuge in dreams as a flight from reality. Nietzsche in fact cites Pascal, for whom, in order to be happy, all it would take would be to dream every night of being king, but he then admits that this dominion of art over life, however delightful, would be a deception. Or else, and this
is what Nietzsche‘s heirs have accepted as his true lesson, art can say what it says because it is Being itself, in its weakness and generosity, that accepts any definition, and enjoys seeing itself perceived as mutable, a dreamer, extenuatingly vigorous and victoriously weak, no longer as fullness, presence or foundation, but rather as fracture, absence of foundation, work and pain. Which is the position of the last (or at least of
the more lucid) of the Nietzscheans, GianniVattimo. Being can therefore only be spoken insofar as it is in decline; instead of imposing itself, it withdraws. Thus we have arrived at an ontology organized into .weak‘ categories. Nietzsche‘s announcement of the death of God is nothing more than the proclamation of the end
of the stable structure of Being. From now on, Being will present itself only as suspension and withdrawal.

The trouble is, in the first place, that, once we had settled our accounts with the World, we would still find ourselves having to settle them with the subject that emits that flatus vocis (a problem which is in any case the limit of any magic idealism). And, in the second place, if it is there a hermeneutic principle by which there are no facts but only interpretations, this still does not exclude the possibility of ―bad. interpretations. There is no winning hand at poker that has not been put together by a choice of the player (encouraged maybe by chance), but this does not mean that every hand assembled by the player is a winning hand. All it would take is for my opponent to respond to my three aces with a straight flush for my wager to turn out to have been
a bad bet. There are times in our game with the World when the World responds to our three aces with a straight flush. Furthermore, there are players who place a bet and are eventually obliged to show a hand that, according to the laws of poker, contains no valid combination of cards: and the others, in unison, observe that the player must be crazy, or doesn‘t know how to play, or is bluffing. What is the status of bluffing in a universe in which one interpretation is as good as another? What are the inter-subjective criteria that allow us to define that particular combination of cards as off the wall? What criterion allows us to distinguish between dreams, poetic inventions and LDS acid trips (there are people who after taking LSD have thrown themselves out of windows convinced they could fly and finished up in a heap on the sidewalk—contrary, mind you, to all their hopes and intentions), and, on the other hand, acceptable statements concerning the things of the physical or historical world that surrounds us?

Coming back to Rorty‘s screwdriver, my objection did not denied that it can permit manifold interpretations, so that I could use it also to commit a homicide. The only thing that is, even though possible at least inexpedient, is that I‘ll use it to scratch my ear and first of all I cannot use it to transport a liquid matter as I could do with a glass (as well as I cannot use a paper glass to throw it in order to crash a window). My
remarks are not trivial at all even though they look as mere truism: they mean that a screwdriver answers positively (so to speak) to many of my possible interpretations, bat in certain cases says NO.

This sort of refusal opposed by the objects of our world is the basis of my prudent idea of a Negative Realism.

Remember that not even Nietzsche denied the existence of terrible forces that constantly press upon us. In my Kant and the Platypus I called these terrible forces the hard core of Being.

In speaking of a ―hard core. I did not mean something like a ―stable kernel. which we might identify sooner or later, not the Law of Laws, but, more prudently, lines of resistance that render some of our approaches fruitless. It is precisely our faith in these lines of resistance that ought also to guide the discourse on hermeneutics, because, if we assumed that one can say anything and that ―everything goes., the
intellectual and moral tension that guides our continual interrogation of the World (even if we consider Being as something that continually vanishes and escapes our grasp) would no longer make sense. We should in any case admit the presence of that


Something, even though that Something shows up as mere absence. It would be an absence we constantly chase.

When we claim to have learned from experience that nature exhibits stable tendencies, there is no need to think of complex laws like the law of universal gravity, but of experiences that are simpler and more immediate, like the apparent rising and setting of the sun, the fact that things fall downwards and not upwards, the existence of species. Universals may well be a figment and an infirmity of thought, and could
be a mistake to figure out such species as ―cat. or ―dog.. In spite of this we know by experience that if we unite a dog with a dog what is born is a dog, and if we unite a dog with a cat nothing is born—and even if something were born it would be unable to reproduce. This does not yet mean that what we have recognized is the reality (Darwinian or Platonic) of genera and species. All it is meant to suggest is that speaking per generalia may well be a result of our penuria nominum (as the Medieval said) , but that something resistant has driven us to invent general terms (whose extension we can always revise and correct). The objection that biotechnology may one day render these tendencies obsolete and create a new species halfway between a
cat and a dog is not relevant. The fact that a technology, which by definition alters the limits of nature, is required in order to violate them means that the limits of nature exist.

To state that there are lines of resistance merely means to say that, even if it appears only as an effect of language, Being is not an effect of language in the sense that language freely constructs it. Even those who stated that Being is pure Chaos, and therefore susceptible to all discourse, would at least have to exclude that it is Order. Language does not construct being ex novo: it questions it, in some way always finding something already given. Even if Being were moth-eaten (as Vattimo once suggested by a brilliant metaphor), there would always be a fabric whose warp and web, confused by the infinite holes that have eaten into it, still subsist in some stubborn way.

This already given is in fact what we have called the lines of resistance. The appearance of these Resistances is the nearest thing that can be found, before any First


Philosophy or Theology, to the idea of God or Law. Certainly it is a God who manifests himself as pure Negativity, pure Limit, pure ―No., that of which language cannot or must not talk. In this sense it is something very different from the God of the revealed religions, or it assumes only His severest traits, those of the exclusive Lord of Interdiction, incapable of saying so much as ―go forth and multiply., but only
intent on repeating ―thou shalt not eat from this tree..

This idea of lines of resistance, by which something which does not depend on our interpretations challenges them, can represent a form of Minimal or Negative Realism according to which facts, if scarcely tell me if I am right, frequently tell I me that I am wrong.

Suppose that on that wall we see a half-open door. Many interpretations are possible, first that it is a real door, second that it is a painted door - but if we entertain this second interpretation we must still decide whether it is a case of trompe-l‘oeil, intending to deceive us, or if it is an artistic representation of a door, a fresco that asks for an aesthetic response. There are other possible interpretations (was the door painted recently, should we consider it a masterpiece or a daub? – and so on and so forth). But suppose we entertain the interpretation that that is a real door and go straight ahead in order to pass through. The very fact that we smash our nose is the proof that our interpretation was wrong.

That is the minimal or negative realism, which not only concerns our knowledge of simple facts but also our knowledge of texts – that is not only our perception of a dog but also our reading of a book. Infinite are our possible interpretations of Finnegans Wake but even the most savage deconstructionist cannot say that it tells the story of a French lady who read love stories, commits adultery and poisons herself. In my book the Limits of interpretations (published more than 20 years ago) I make many examples of interpretations which are definitely disproved by the text we are trying to interpret. And 50 years ago when I started to be interested on the initiative of the reader and of forms of art conceived in order to elicit infinite interpretations, the title of my book was Opera aperta, The Open Wok: the title clearly suggests that the open series of interpretations that a work of art encourages is continually obliged to


confront itself with the presence of work, that is of an object produced before its interpretations, produced in order to promote but at the same time to control them.

How can we admit that there are facts I am interpreting which can challenge me by some limits? This could be a mere postulate of interpretation, since if we assumed that we can say everything of everything then the adventure of our continuous questioning of the world would miss of any reason. At this point even the most radical of relativists could be justified in assuming the point of view of the most radical of old fashioned realists, because – if anything goes - there would be no philosophical difference between being a Leninist or a deconstructionist.

But we have the experience of an undeniable Limit in front of which our languages evaporate into silence and it is the experience of Death. We question the World being sure, by a millenary experience, that all men are mortal, and Death is the Limit after which all the interpreting initiatives vanish. Therefore, by knowing for
sure that there is at least one limit that challenges the infinite progress of our interpretation, we are encouraged to keep on by suspectiing that there are other limits to the freedom of our conjectures.

It is not necessary to support what I am saying by any other metaphysical theory but rather by a semiotic one, that of Hjelmslev. We use signs (or expressions) to convey a content, and this content is carved out and organized in different forms by different cultures (and languages). What is it made from? From an amorphous stuff, amorphous before language has carried out its vivisection of it. Let us to call such an amorphous stuff, which we will call the continuum of the content, all that may be experienced, said, and thought: as the infinite horizon, if you will, of that which is, has been and will be, both out of necessity and contingency. It would seem that before a culture has organized it linguistically in the form of content, this continuum is everything and nothing, and therefore eludes all determination.

Nevertheless, when Hjelmslev speaks of this amorphous continuum that every language organizes in a different way, he says that linguistic chains such as I do not know, je ne sais pas, en tieda, naluvara, jeg ved det ikke, despite their differences, express the same mening, that is, the same thought. The Danish term mening should


be translated as meaning and Hielmslev for the English version of his work accepted the term purport. How can an amorphous continuum have a meaning or a purport?

As a matter of fact Hjelmslev was not speaking of a linguistic phenomenon but rather of an extra-linguistic one: he said that the purport could be described by various extra-linguistic disciplines. Thus languages are obliged to recognize extra-semiotic constrictions that they cannot ignore. In other words different expressions such as it is raining, il pleut and piove all refer to the same phenomenon. As if to say that in the magma of the continuum there are lines of resistance and possibilities for flow, like the grain in wood or marble that makes it easier to cut it one way rather than another. Every culture runs up against the extra-linguistic problem of rain, it rains or doesn‘t rain in every culture, and tertium datur only when it drizzles or when hoar-frost
forms.

If the continuum itself has lines of tendency, we are not entitled to say whatever we like. There are directions, maybe not compulsory directions, but certainly directions that are forbidden. There are things we cannot say. It doesn‘t matter if these things were once said. We subsequently ―banged our heads into. evidence that
convinced us that we could no longer say what we formerly said.

If so, Being may not be comparable to a one-way street but to a network of multi-lane freeways along which one can travel in more than one direction; but despite this some roads will nonetheless remain dead-ends.

Here we should avoid a misunderstanding. When we talk of the experience of something that obliges us to recognize the grain and lines of resistance, and to formulate laws, by no means are we claiming that these laws adequately represent the lines of resistance. As if to say that, if along the path running through the wood, I find a boulder blocking the way, I must certainly turn right or left (or decide to turn back), but this gives me absolutely no assurance that the decision taken will help me know the wood better. The incident simply interrupts a project of mine and persuades me to think up another one. To state that there are lines of resistance does not yet mean, as


Peirce would have said, that there are universal laws at work in nature. The hypothesis of universal laws (or the hypothesis of a specific law) is only one of the ways in which we react to the onset of a resistance. But Habermas, in his search for the kernel of Peirce‘s criticism of the Kantian thing-in-itself, emphasizes that the Peircean problem is not that something (concealed behind the appearances that would mirror it) has, like a mirror, a rear side that eludes reflection, a side that we are almost sure we will one day discover, as long as we manage to get round the figure we see: it is that reality imposes restrictions on our cognition only in the sense that it refuses false interpretations.

I believe that there are some connections between my idea of a Negative Realism and Popper‘s idea by which the only real proof for the acceptability of our scientific hypotheses is their possibility to support a test of falsifiability. But I also think that my notion of a minimal realism can be translated in terms of the philosophy of Peirce. Remember that according to Peirce every of our enquiries, as well as of our
perceptual explorations of the surrounding world, is elicited by a Dynamical Object. We do not know it if not through Immediate Obiects, that are signs, either mental phenomena or translations of a previous Immediate Object into another which is its interpretant – so that the series of interpretants never stops, by producing a process of unlimited semiosis. However by producing these interpretants we grow a habit, that is, an ability to act upon the sorrounding reality, and the proof that a given series of interpretants works is given by the fact that through our habit we can modify the reality. If this does not succeed, it means that our nterpretations were dominated by the continuous risk of fallibilism. The possibility of a failure means that there is something controlling and limiting our interpretations.

We still do not know whether neutrinos travel faster than light and we need new experiments and new interpretations of new data. But if at a certain point we cannot act positively by assuming that neutrinos are faster than light, it means that such an hypothesis must be rejected.

Is it enough to entertain such a notion of Minimal Realism in order to conceive both of an open enquiry and of the hope to reach some day or another some truth?


Once Searle said that realism means that we are convinced that things go in a certain way, maybe we will never know definitely how they go, but we are sure that they will go that way even if we shall never know how they go. Maybe this is not enough to believe, with Peirce, that in the long run maybe we can attains some truth; but it is enough to prudently to assume, by the idea of a Negative Realism, that there is something that it would be crazy to say.